Law, Politics, and Philosophy

Tuguegarao City, Cagayan. Atty. MICHAEL JHON M. TAMAYAO manages this blog. Contact: mjmtamayao@yahoo.com.

Ancient Greek Philosophy

ORIGIN

AND DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY IN ANCIENT GREECE

Myths and the Birth of Science and Philosophy…

Myths have always been part of human consciousness. Before the Spaniards introduced Christianity to the Philippines, Filipinos have embraced myths as a rule of life. The myth of “Bathala”, for example, was firmly believed as the explanation of how man and the world came to be. “Bathala”, the supreme being bestowed with all the superlative qualities, was then seen as the ultimate “cause” of everything. For our ancestors, myths were the “accepted explanations” for the various cosmological and social phenomena. They were seen as “the truths” that ground reality. This mythological predisposition has been so engrained in our Filipino mindset that traces of it can still be observed today. Whenever beset by a seemingly unsolvable predicament, we Filipinos often say “bahala na” (anything goes), firmly believing that everything will be well with the grace of the Almighty. The word “bahala” is obviously a modern rendition of “Bathala” which alludes to the fact that the phrase “bahala na” also means “Bathala (God) will take care of everything.” Indeed myths shaped, not only the world-view of our ancestors, but also our modern life-worlds.

2500 years ago, mythological explanations were also widespread in Greece, the heart of the ancient western civilization. Before it became the much-applauded scientific and philosophical culture, Greece was ardently a mythological culture. Spearheaded by the likes of Hesiod and Homer, Greeks viewed the world from a very complex mythological perspective. Famous gods and goddesses like Zeus and Athena, and Aphrodite and Aries were all Greek concoctions that served as uncontested rationalizations for all the natural phenomena.

However, something remarkable and “unthinkable” happened in Miletus, a small corner of a Greek colony in Asia Minor – man suddenly began to think “scientifically” and “philosophically.” This was a moment (considered as a gift to mankind) which totally changed the course of human history. Until today, no one still knows why or how this happened; it continues to be a mystery – a blessing, I can say – that elevated man into a higher state of consciousness.

Some scholars say that the flourishing economic condition of sixth-century Miletus was the impetus for the emergence of science and philosophy in Greece. Veritably, wealth stimulates not only the economic growth of a nation but also its intellectual and cultural development. The Greeks began to ask questions which “busy” and “preoccupied” minds cannot ask; questions like “why are we here?”, “where did everything come from?”, and “what is the underlying stuff of all things?” While the slaves did all the manual labors, the citizens concentrated on knowledge and culture. The citizens were not contended with the myths, so they sought for explanations that answered forthrightly their problems. Thus a change from a mythologically imagined world to a world grasped scientifically and philosophically took place in Greece.

Science and philosophy were not yet distinguished during that time. The Greek philosophers simply saw both disciplines as man’s passionate disposition towards the acquisition of “wisdom.” Their entanglement proved to be very fruitful and find their visible significance in the natural philosophers.

The Archê Project: The Quest for the “Underlying Stuff” of Nature…

Thales

According to Aristotle, “Thales of Miletus” (624-547 BC) was the first scientist and philosopher, for he was the first person to investigate on the originating principle (archê) of things. He was often acclaimed as the “Father of Science” and the founder of the school of natural philosophy or Cosmology (study of the “ordered” universe). He has varied interests, investigating on almost all fields of knowledge. In Plato’s Republic, Thales was described as a man who has “many and ingenious inventions for arts and business of life.” He traveled in many places including Egypt and Babylon from which he acquired knowledge in engineering, geometry, agriculture and astronomy. He excelled in the domain of applied science as he accurately predicted a solar eclipse in May 28, 585 BC. He was so highly esteemed that Plutrach, a well known historian and ancient scholar, named him, together with the likes of Socrates and Aristotle, as one of the Seven Sages of ancient times. And as the letter cited by Diogenes Laertius purported, all scientific and philosophical discourses begin with Thales’ treatises.

One of the main reasons why Thales was well-regarded during his time was because of his revolutionary defiance against commonly accepted conjectures and myths. His original views and hypotheses about nature were excitingly new, on the basis of which Aristotle recognized him and his ideas as the genesis of scientific investigation.

Thales’ natural philosophy is well-known for his infamous statement, “all things are full of gods.” Although this statement sounds “mythological,” its real import served as the catalyst for scientific thinking. His position challenged the validity and relevance of myths in explaining the natural world. The idea of “god in things” rejects the idea of an “external god” which causes the changes in the physical world, and supports explanations inferred from the natural conditions of things themselves. The answer for Thales is not “outside” nature but “inside” nature itself.

“God in things” also suggests that things are life-like insofar as their change or behavior is intelligible and predictable. Things are predictable because they follow a pattern of unbroken “causality.” Things are causes (aitia) of other things so that all the transformations are ordered as to their causes. Thales emphasizes on the intimate connection of predictability and causality, which are now two of the most important concepts in modern sciences. It is precisely for this reason that we can discern the philosophico-scientific significance of Thales’ assertion.

Thales was an extreme thinker, inasmuch as he wanted to find the “ultimate cause of all things.” Unlike the doctors and astronomers who only sought for the “proximate causes” of diseases and cosmic changes, the philosopher Thales sought for “the” cause, the “underlying stuff” that connected all things together. “Order out of chaos”, this was the motif of his philosophy; it was the search for that underlying stuff which ordered nature that concerned him and the subsequent natural philosophers the most.

What is the underlying stuff of nature?

The Water-Thesis

In order to answer this highly “theoretical” question, Thales reverted back to the domain of observational experience. In his journeys he observed that life sprung from where water was. Crops and vegetables grew near rivers. Frogs and worms appeared every after the rain poured. Great civilizations like Egypt, Mesopotamia, and India thrived near bodies of water. Living creatures, such as plants, animals and men, are mostly made-up of moist. Rivers also generate earth, as Thales might have observed when he saw coastal lands grow in each passing year. Ultimately, water nourishes everything in the cosmos. Thus Thales concluded that water was “the underlying stuff” of nature; or, as Aristotle wrote in his Metaphysics, for Thales “all things are water.” Nature as water is a single material substance, manifested in a myriad of ways which water can turn into. Water after all was a substance that can take all the various forms of matter (solid, liquid and gas) and as such the major component of all things. The fact for Thales was that all things were mere manifestations of water.

His water-thesis may seem naive for us today, but his views, if put against the background of ancient mythology from which it drastically departed, were innovative and revolutionary to say the least.

Anaximander’s Boundless

After Thales various Milesian philosophers proposed their own versions of the “underlying stuff.” Anaximander (610-546 BC), believed to be a student of Thales and the second Milesian philosopher, stated that the “boundless” (apeiron) united everything in nature. We do not and cannot exactly say what Anaximander meant by this “boundless” but one thing was for sure, that the ordering cause of nature was not a single substance but an “infinity” of constant encroachments. For him the various elements of nature (water, earth, fire and air) were constantly opposing each other in a battle for dominance. Nature is constantly changing but its changes (the opposition of the different elements) will in the end produce a balance.

The notion of “boundless” or “infinity” also goes beyond the “finitude” of created things. Created things are limited in the sense that they are perishable. Things that are perishable constantly change and that which continually changes is unintelligible. If what we are seeking is an “intelligible cause” that unites and goes beyond the multiplicity of the physical world, then the only possible answer is something “infinite,” “uncreated” or, for Anaximander, the “boundless.”

Anaximenes’ Air of Life

Another Milesian philosopher proposed that “air” or “vapour” was the underlying stuff of all things. His name was Anaximenes (570-526 BC), the third Milesian philosopher. For Anaximenes, air, which was and continued to be the most dominant element in the universe, was the origin of earth, water and fire. Water was just condensed air or the compact form of vapour (air). Earth was also a condensed form of air, more condense than water. Anaximenes figured this out by observing that when the snow melted the earth emerged. And fire, the last element in the list, was rarefied air. Its air molecules – using a more modern term – were less dense than water and earth.

For the old worlds, air was not just the source of life; it represented life itself. This idea was not only embraced by the west but also by the east. The author of the book of Genesis, for example, an Israelite, spoke of God as blowing into man’s nostrils the “breath” or “air” of life. The connection of air and life was so intimate that separating them is inconceivable. Air must therefore be the grounding element of life and reality.

Material Monism

This theory unique to Milesian cosmologies that relies on a single material substance in explaining the unity of things is called Material Monism. The several substances (earth, water, air, fire, etc) and the varied changes in nature are just modifications of the single material stuff that is always and everywhere present. Can you think of other substances which can in your own opinion be an answer to this ancient question?

GUIDE QUESTIONS:

1. Is there any difference between science and philosophy during the time of the Milesian philosophers? Why?

2. Why was Thales’ “water thesis” important?

3. What are the proposals of the various Milesian philosophers for the archê or underlying stuff of things?

Change and Permanence…

Central to Thales’ view of reality was the idea of “One” in the “Many,” i.e., that there was one unchanging thing that serves as the principle cause of the many changing things. On the one hand, there was Permanence and, on the other hand, there was Change. Two subsequent philosophers embraced these two sides of Thales’ view; Heraclitus focused on the side of change, while Parmenides, on the side of permanence.

i. Heraclitus

Heraclitus accepted Thales’ notion that there was “one” underlying stuff behind the “many” observable things. For him the reality of one cause was demanded by reason, and the reality of the many changing things was demanded by sense experience. His eyes saw the changes but his mind saw the order behind those changes. Indeed, there must be “one” among the “many.”

But for Heraclitus this “one” cause was not “unchanging”; it was also changing. The orderly changes in nature cannot possibly have one “unchanging” cause because evidently everything, how orderly it may be, changes. Thales was then looking for the “one” underlying stuff which accounted for the order in the change but at the same time was also “changing”. For him this one changing stuff was “fire.”

Fire is a continually changing substance but simultaneously remains as one single thing. Whereas Thales’ notion of water involved his reversion from abstract reason to sense experience, Heraclitus’ idea of fire was perfectly consistent to sense experience. The perfect balance and connectivity of reason and sense experience found its way into Heraclitus’ ingenious concoction of fire as the “one changing stuff.”

In Fragment 76, Heraclitus said, “Fire lives the death of earth, and air the death of fire, water lives the death of air, earth that of water.” This assertion simply points to the fact that in the rational cycle of change nothing is ever lost or gained. In fire, life and death continue in an endless cycle. Fire is the cause of the continuous and eternal change. This prompted Heraclitus to say that fire in itself has a “living logos (reason)” that makes the natural world appear intelligible.

Eventually Heraclitus linked fire with God. If fire possesses a “living reason” that made natural changes intelligible, fire must be the bond that united everything, including “opposites” – love and strife, war and peace, beauty and ugliness, black and white, freedom and imprisonment. But there can be no other being capable of becoming this ultimate bond than God himself. God is “day and night, winter and summer, war and peace, fullness and hunger.” Thus, Heraclitus’ philosophy culminated in the equation, “Fire = Logos = God.”

ii. Parmenides

While Heraclitus wholly embraced the idea of “change”, Parmenides completely rejected its intelligibility. For the latter, “change is impossible.” This is because it involves the absurd idea that something comes into being and goes out of being. Relying strictly on the dictates of his reason, Parmenides rebuffed what his sense perception dictated and went on defending his out-of-this-world statement, “change is impossible”!

For Parmenides, both Thales and Heraclitus’ notion of “One” in the “Many” is problematic. The “One” is not the “Many” and the “Many” cannot be “One.” This is a self-evident proposition. Furthermore, Parmenides identified the “One” with what is – with Reality or Being. Reality or Being is not just this or that or even the collection of all things. Reality is the living condition, our encounter with the world and the things at hand. Reality is a happening; a dynamic process that lets the things at hand become something significant, i.e. something “there.” Reality therefore is not just some graspable or perceptible thing but it is simply what is, the on-going presencing. But although Reality or Being has extension, i.e. it manifests itself in particular things, it does not have particular qualities. It is just “one undifferentiated happening” and not “many.”

Being or Reality cannot change because if it changes then it will become Being or non-Being (what is not). Being cannot become Being because it is already Being, and Being cannot become non-Being because there will be “no thing” (non-Being) for it to turn into. Being will still be Being. To put it in simpler terms, if “something” (Being) will change, then it does not change at all because there is “no thing” (non-Being) for it to change into.

With all these complex assertions, Parmenides only wanted to state a self-evident truth – “what  is is (Being is Being) and what is not is not (non-Being is non-Being) as that what is not cannot be what is (Being cannot be Nothing).” Under Parmenides’ deductions therefore change, which incorporates the idea that what is can come into being and go out of being, is theoretically impossible. The inevitable consequence of this proposition is to deny the data perceived by our senses. Changes are just illusions.

iii. The Heraclitean and Parmenidean Influence to Science

Modern day science exhibits the Heraclitean emphasis on sense experience. Just like Heraclitus, modern scientists emphasize knowledge gained from observational corroboration, and support the “empirical spirit” of science which fosters greater stress on sense perception and discourages pure speculative theory.

Parmenides, on the other hand, was the first philosopher who distinguished non-Being from Being and who argued that only the latter was strictly knowable. Science today firmly abides by this Parmenidean dictum such that only “something” – and not “no thing” – is the “object” of science. Furthermore, Parmenides also underscored the fact, a fact limitedly recognized by Thales and Heraclitus, that knowledge about reality must go beyond a percepception of changing material thing.

VI. Atomism

Aside from Sophism, there was also a budding group of thinkers in Greece called the “Atomists.” Leucippus (490-430 B.C.) was said to be the founder of this school of thought, and then it was influentially developed by Democritus. For some, atomism is the first authentic, scientific view of the world.

i. Democritus

The Atomistic philosophy is commonly associated with Democritus. While Protagoras held that “man is the measure of all things”, Democritus believed that “man knows nothing,” for all that he knows are mere opinions.

The seeds of Atomism can be found in the philosophies of Heraclitus and Parmenides. On the one hand, Democritus’ Atomism saw the manifoldness of reality in Heraclitus’ notion of change. On the other hand, Democritus also accepted Parmenides’ notion of an unchanging dimension of reality. For Democritus, there were very tiny atoms unseen by the naked eye that were “internally unchanging” and which “composed all the changing visible things we perceive.” For him, “atoms” were the answer to the venerable question of the “one in the many.” It was the “One” because it was internally unchanging, eternal, indestructible, and without emptiness. It was a material object, the smallest material component of things which cannot be divided into smaller parts. It was also the reason for the “Many” inasmuch as the perceivable things were ultimately caused to change, and to behave in predictable ways, by the mechanical forces of atoms.

In a way, Democritus sought to reunite once again the two sorts of realities and modes of knowing then. Reality has One unchanging stuff but also has many perceivable changes. The permanent “one” is known through reason, while the perceivable changes (Many) are perceived by the senses.

ii. Atomistic Materialism

For the Atomists, matter, without any intrinsic reason or purpose, is the sole reality. This is now the pervading theory of reality of modern science. The world is not composed of spirits or ruled by unseen forces but it is governed by mechanical forces called atoms. This also applies to the reality of man. Man does not have dual nature, the flesh and soul; he is purely a material object, only that he is more complex than the others.

Atomism held that knowledge was not based on an “immaterial faculty of reason.” Man acquired knowledge using a “material sort of reason.” This sounds degrading but Democritus firmly asserted that reason was just a higher form of “perception” or, as he calls it, “trueborn” perception. Thus, knowledge was simply seen as perception.

iii. Problems with Atomism

What is immediately implied in the Atomist materialism is that “everything is mechanically determined.” It is generally accepted that matter is governed by the law of causality. Matter is always a cause of another. This is self-evident. This pattern, which is fervently embraced by matter, accounts for their predictable behavior.

The building block of all matter is atom, so that all perceptible material entities, including human beings, are configurations of atoms. Moreover, atoms are impelled by mechanical forces to act on one another. This then makes all material movements, including human “actions”, as causally determined. Thus, human freedom and moral actions are irrelevant under the Atomistic materialism.

Truth is also reduced to perception in Atomism. This makes even the human faculty of reason a material function and hence reduces man to a soul-less machine, doing what it was determined to do and acting out of a determined set of laws.

But looking at the positive side, Atomism stressed the importance of perception in the acquisition of knowledge. True enough, nothing is known unless it passes through the senses.

V. Sophism and Relativism…

The philosophical epoch where Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes, Heraclitus and Parmenides belonged is called the Pre-Socratic period. This epoch was called as such because it was a period that came before Socrates, one of the greatest philosopher-thinkers to have walked this planet. Socrates fought for the validity of “universal” ideas as opposed to “relativistic” ideas proposed by the so-called “Sophists,” the learned teachers and masters of rhetoric in ancient Greece. They were known as “relativists” because “truth” for them was based on how “you” present a position and persuade your listeners to believe on your truth claim. As they see it, truth favors the influential, learned and persuasive individual or group of individuals. Among several prominent Sophists was Protagoras.

i. Protagoras

Protagoras, as described by Plato, was “a man of wide experience, deep learning, and original thought.” Indeed, Protagoras has “original thought” when he stated that “man is the measure of all things.” His statement may have become all too common already but its meaning has become ever too elusive. In its simplest sense, the statement meant truth varied from one man to another, for every man has his own interpretation or “measure” of the truth of things. From him, there was no objective way in resolving which perspective was true because each person was entitled to his own truth. Although you may have the same assertions as mine, it will just redound to the fact that agreements are rooted in our “subjective” perception and not in what is “objectively” true about the world.

Relativity finds its roots in Protagoras’ notion of “measurement” in the phrase “man is the measure of all things.” “Measurement” in the statement is primarily associated with sense perception and not with reason. As such, no question can be universally true because all measurements from sense perception vary. But every assertion is “subjectively” true because it holds true to every individual.

We may argue that Protagoras is proposing a very inconsistent system of thought. Under his system, everybody is left to his own with no standards to follow. But looking from a wider perspective, Protagoras is simply making a more realistic description of human knowledge – that it can never be absolute. True enough, man can never possess an absolute knowledge of reality for the simple reason that we are finite and reality is infinite. Thus man can but only give bits of what reality is and never the whole of it.

ii. Extreme and Moderate relativism

Protagoras’ relativism can be understood in two ways: first, as extreme (irrational) relativism, and, second, as moderate (rational) relativism. From the point of view of extreme relativism, there is no such thing as “Reality” because truth is only based on man’s propositions. What is real is what I say it is. Rational relativism, on the other hand, affirms the existence of “Reality” and adds that this reality cannot be limited to a “single characterization.” So unlike extreme relativism which ascribes truth to all propositions (because it rejects reality), moderate relativism holds that all propositions are true because there is a “complex reality” which cannot be fully comprehended. All assertions for the latter are affirmed because it adds understanding to all the possible dimensions of reality. Thus, while the root of relativism for “extreme relativism” is the non-existence of reality, the root of relativism for “moderate relativism” is the complexity of reality.

ii. Implications of Relativism

Relativism is for some a very dangerous philosophy that could lead to many damaging consequences. Moralists and statesmen, most especially, abhor this way of thinking because it prevents the establishment of a “universal norm” that distinguishes good from bad actions. For them, relativism destroys the idea of “order”, for it topples down the existence of laws which are bases for universal, moral and political accord. Without “norms” there will be no basis for order and declaration of laws. This is precisely the terrible thing about relativism – it abandons any objective or rational standards in morality and politics.

The good point of relativism, however, is that it develops the art of rhetoric for clear and forceful use of language. True enough, if one speaks clearly and forcefully, then others can easily accept or reject that which is clearly understood. While the device of the relativists can be used to deceive, it can be used for the pursuance of truth as well.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s

Information

This entry was posted on January 29, 2009 by in Uncategorized.

Profile

tamayaocsu

tamayaocsu

Tuguegarao City, Cagayan Atty. MICHAEL JHON M. TAMAYAO manages this blog. He is currently starting his private law practice. Contact: mjmtamayao@yahoo.com; Tel. No. 09353343739. PROFILE: Atty. Tamayao is currently teaching law, philosophy and social sciences at the Cagayan State University. He finished his Bachelor of Arts in Philosophy degree at the Faculty of Philosophy, University of Santo Tomas and graduated in 2005, garnering the highest academic honors in that Academic Year. He pursued Licentiate in Philosophy and Master of Arts in Philosophy degrees at the same university, completing them both in 2007. In 2009, he took up Bachelor of Laws and Letter at the Cagayan State University, where he also teaches. He passed the 2013 bar exams, and now currently taking up Master of Laws and Letters at the San Beda Graduate School of Law.

View Full Profile →

Calendar

January 2009
M T W T F S S
« Aug   Feb »
 1234
567891011
12131415161718
19202122232425
262728293031  
%d bloggers like this: